Introduction
“No one truly understands entropy.” David Newman
(loosely paraphrased)
When I first heard these words in class, I was intrigued
and decided to make it my personal mission to understand
entropy and what about it makes it such an elusive concept
to grasp. What I found strange was if entropy was such a
difficult concept, how is it that we are able to solve
systems using entropy and calculate relative values for
entropy in a system? It seemed to me that if we can use
entropy to better understand the universe, we must have a
pretty good understanding of what entropy is. But at the
same time, there must be a reason why people often say
that entropy is a difficult concept.
To get a better understanding of entropy, I decided to
take a philosophical approach rather than a mathematical
approach. Basically, what this means is that instead of
trying to lay out mathematical equations illustrating the
process of entropy, I will simply ask questions about
entropy through linguistic analysis, which is a method of
understanding a concept through how the word that denotes
the concept is used in a language. Understanding how
entropy is used as a word is key to understanding entropy
itself. This assumption is jumping across hundreds of
years of philosophic debate starting from Descartes who
challenged all of what we know and what we can know
through the senses. Unfortunately, I cannot go into
all the details of how we can make this assumption, but I
will try and give a quick outline of the basic problem.
Descartes asks us if we ever had a dream where we are
unsure if we are awake or dreaming. He then states that
even if we are sure we are awake, it is still possible
that we are dreaming. Then he creates a hypothetical evil
demon that corrupts not only our senses, but our emotions,
our beliefs, and our memories. Everything that arises in
the mind then becomes susceptible to doubt. But something
that cannot be doubted is the fact that I think that I
think something. In other words, “I see an apple” can be
doubted, but “I think I see an apple” cannot be doubted.
This is where the famous phrase “I think therefore, I am”
comes from. From there, Descartes attempts to create an
indubitable, firm foundation for knowledge.
The obvious problem with Descartes’s thought experiment is
that we live day to day with perfect confidence that what
we experience is true without any doubts. But how is it
that we are sure that what we experience is not a figment
of some demon’s imagination? Let’s say that you have a
friend, Bob. He is a very good friend but no one seems to
be able to see him. This troubles you so much that you
decide to see a doctor. Sorry, but Bob does not exist, off
to the mental hospital you go. But you can argue why we
reject your experience in favor of everyone else’s? The
answer to this is the basis of logical positivism and also
for the scientific method. An object, a principle, a
situation needs to be verifiable before we can accept as a
fact. But this still does not answer the question of how
we can accept that there are other people that can verify
what you experience. (An interesting answer to this
question, and also to the idea that humans have free will
is from Jean-Paul Sartre, and I recommend reading the book
Being or Nothingness.)
One answer is given by the private language argument,
which states that there can be no private language. The
words that are used and the rules of grammar must be used
by a community of language users. Let me explain this in
more depth with Wittgenstein’s Beetle in a Box thought
experiment. Let us pretend that everyone in a classroom
has a “beetle in a box.” No one has ever shown their
“beetle” to any of their classmates, but they are all sure
that what they have in their box is a beetle. The question
then is, does the word, “beetle,” have any meaning? You
can try defining beetle by saying, it is the thing inside
the box, but that does not answer the question of what the
thing is; this respons only gives the thing a
location. The truth is that the “beetle” in this
case is a meaningless concept and the point Wittgenstein
is trying to make, I think, is that the word “beetle”
would never have been created unless everyone using that
language knew what it is the word “beetle” is referring
to. This thought experiment is addressing the classic
philosophical argument which states that my sensations are
private and that no one else has access to them (e.g., no
one can know my pain but myself). But this idea can be
applied to all private language arguments.
In a way, entropy can be thought of as a kind of beetle in
a box (though the analogy is not perfect), in that we use
the word “entropy” blindly without really understanding
what the other person is referring to when they speak of
it. So far, I have not yet begun my analysis of entropy, I
have simply been attempting to provide the justification
that a linguistic analysis of entropy is sufficient for an
understanding of entropy itself. While this justification
is not at all complete, it will be
enough for what I am trying to accomplish, which is have
an understanding of what entropy is.